John Fiske
Realism
(from УTelevision CultureФ, Chapter 2)
The Hart to Hart segment is
"realistic," not because it reproduces reality, which it clearly does
not, but because it reproduces the dominant sense of reality. We can thus call television an essentially realistic medium
because of its ability to carry a socially
convincing sense of the real. Realism is not a matter of any fidelity to an empirical reality, but of the discursive
conventions by which and for which a sense of
reality is constructed.
The most obvious is that it presents itself as an
unmediated picture of external reality. This
view of television realism is often expressed by the metaphors of
transparency or reflection Ч television is seen either as a transнparent window on the world or as a mirror
reflecting our own reality back to us.
It is significant that both these metaphors invoke a sheet of glass as an impersonal, noncultural
medium of reproduction - the human or cultural agency in the process is masked: this means that the finished
representation is naturalized, that
it is made to appear the result of natural rather than cultural processes, it is taken away from the realm of
history and culture and moved towards
that of universal truth. Taking the metaphors to their logical extreme like
this reveals their obvious inadequacy to explain the way that television gives us representations of the world, but some
professionals still cling to what
media theorists call "the transparency fallacy" (the first of our
metaнphors), and the use of the
reflection one is quite common even in relatively thoughtful discussions of the medium. The way that
I phrased it at the beginning of this
paragraph does allow it some validity, for it does assume that it is our reality, not the reality, that is reflected; in other words it admits that reality is the product of people, and not a
universal object that people merely
observe from the outside. What I wish to do in this chapter is to study the ways by which television produces
"reality" rather than reflects it.
Realism can be defined in a number of ways, for
it is actually a fairly slippery concept
capable of a variety of inflections. Ian Watt (1957) and Raymond Williams (1977) tend to define it by its content. Watt traces
its origins to the rise of the novel in the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Realism
developed alongside empiricism, individualism, humanism, and the bourgeoisie,
so it is not surprising that it should share characteristics with all of them. For Watt realism depends on
the belief in an objective reality that can be accurately experienced by the human senses: this
reality is made up of an infinity of unique objects,
people, places, and actions. So for him realism characteristically represents particular events happening
to individualized people
in specified places and time spans. The senses and experience of the individual
are seen as the prime way of making sense of this universe of phenomena, and if social, moral,
religious, or political ideas intrude, they must always be expressed within the forms of individual
experience.
Raymond Williams (1977), whose historical
perspective covers the nineнteenth and twentieth
centuries, lists three main characteristics of realism in drama: he finds that it has a contemporary setting, that it concerns
itself with secular action Ч that is, with human action described in
exclusively human terms Ч and that it is "socially extended."
By this he means that it deals with the
lives and experiences of ordinary people, not kings and social leaders; in
particular, that inflection of realism which we may call "social
realism" and which Williams's definition is inclining towards deals
with the working class's experience of
subordination in an industrial society. In so far as this is portrayed sympathetically (though not
uncritically), Williams is able to add a fourth characteristic of realism, that it consciously interprets this
experience from a particular political
point of view, normally from the left. The first three characteristics explain realism's particular suitability for
television: television's audience,
like realism's content, is socially extended, unlike the more selective audiences of theater or many cinema
films; television is particularly well suited to representing human action in
human terms - its small screen and
comparatively poor definition lead it to concentrate on mid-shots and close-ups of people acting, reacting, and
interacting. Its repetition and its
origins in studios rather than exterior locations lead it to rely on familiar interior settings of a human domestic
scale that fit comfortably into the family room within which it is
usually viewed. Television typically deals with
the contemporary Ч this holds good as a generalization despite the popularity of historical drama as a genre. Indeed,
critics like Feuer (1983) and Heath and Skirrow (1977) have identified as one of the defining
characнteristics of television its "nowness,"
the sense of being always "live" which it constantly tries to promote. Film presents itself as a record of what
has happened, television presents itself as a relay of what is
happening. Even at the micro level this sense of the present is conveyed
by television's technical processes. Cheaply
produced dramas, such as soaps and sitcoms, are normнally shot with multiple cameras in the studio and
have limited or no post-production
editing. This means that the time taken to perform an action on television coincides precisely with the time taken
to perform it in "real life" -dead time in the middle cannot be
edited out as it is on film. This absence of authorial (or editorial) intervention adds subtly to the sense of realisticness, the sense that the camera is merely recording what
happened, and to the sense
of liveness, that it is happening now Ч the same
perfect match between represented television
time and the lived "real" time of the viewer is, after all, characteristic of genuinely live television, such
as sport.
Marion Jordan (1981), in her excellent discussion
of the social realism of the English soap
opera Coronation Street, lists characteristics that are perfectly
compatible with those of Watt and Williams:
Briefly the genre of Social
Realism demands that life should be presented in the form of a narrative of personal events, each with a beginning, a middle
and an end, important to the central characters concerned but affecting others in only minor ways; that though these events are
ostensibly about social problems they should have as one of their
central concerns the settling of people in
life; that the resolution of these events should always be in terms of the effect of personal interventions; that characters
should be either working-class or of the classes immediately visible to the
working classes (shopkeepers, say, or the
two-man business) and should be credibly accounted for in terms of the "ordinariness" of their homes,
families, friends; that the locale
should be urban and provincial (preferably in the industrial north); that the
settings should be commonplace and recognisable (the pub, the street, the factory, the home and more particularly the kitchen); that the time should be "the
present"; that the style should be such as to suggest an unmediated,
unprejudiced and complete view of reality;
to give, in summary, the impression that the reader, or viewer, has spent some time at the expense of the characters
depicted. (p. 28)
Williams's emphasis on social extension and
Jordan's on the working class should alert us to the fact that most American
television realism is not "social realism"
with its implied criticism of "dominant" realism. Television's world is much more centered on the middle class which
provides its typical content and viewing position.
Our discussion of realism so far has concentrated
on its content and the definition of the social world which it provides. We
have looked at its form only to stress its
so-called transparency. But form is just as much a bearer of meaning and
culture as is content, and many would argue that, as a bearer of ideology, form
is considerably more effective than content. Obviously the definition of the world and the agenda that constitutes the world are
importнant, but it is the form that they are given that
produces the point of view from which we look at them,
and thus the sense we make of them, and, paradoxiнcally,
the sense they make of us. For making sense is always a two-way process: understanding the object necessarily involves defining the
subject who is doing the understanding.
The form of
realism
So realism can be defined by its form, as well
as by its content. This relates it to what it does rather than to what it is or
what it shows (its content). Realism does not just reproduce reality, it makes
sense of it - the essence of realism is that it reproduces reality in such a form as to make it easily
understandable. It does this primarily by ensuring
that all links and relationships between its elements
are clear and logical, that the narrative follows the basic laws of cause and effect, and that every element is there for the purpose of
helping to make sense: nothing is extraneous
or accidental. Thus the flowers in the Harts'
cabin are not just accidental decoration, they signify the Harts' class, taste, and wealth, and they also carry the values of being a popular
hero/ine, those that
constitute attractiveness.
I have assumed that realism is typically narrative in form, and this
assumpнtion holds good; indeed some, such as
Barthes (1975a), imply that realism is always narratival; even a photo or a realistic painting is a
frozen moment in a narrative, and
understanding it involves reconstructing the narrative on either side of the moment presented to us.
This definition of realism is particularly
relevant for television because it admits of
fantasy. Wonderwoman or the Six
Million Dollar Man are "realistic" because their
"fantastic" actions and abilities conform to the laws of cause and effect, they are related logically to other
elements of the narrative, and work according
to what Belsey (1980) calls a "recognizable
system."
Davies (1978/9) develops this point in her
argument that Hollywood cinema appeals as widely as it does not
because it is a visualization of the nineteenth-century
realist novel, but because its realism is able to embody a variety of popular forms:
What we have in Hollywood cinema
is not so much a transference onto the screen
of the dominant realist narrative form (which was principally conн cerned with interior moral life) but a fusing of popular
forms (melodrama, romance, adventure, Gothic thriller, detective story, etc.)
with a realist politique. (p. 61)
Her use of the word "politique" is
significant for it implies that the mode of realism
itself is political, is ideological. The politics lie in the way it "conнtains" the world within Belsey's
"recognizable system." Realism is thus defined by the way it makes sense of the real, rather than by what it
says the real consists of. Watt (1957)
refers to this way of understanding realism when he points to its historical conjuncture with empiricism, individualism, humanism (or secularism), and bourgeois capitalism.
The way we make sense of a realistic text is through the same broad
ideological frame as the way we make sense
of our social experience in the industrialized west (the art of non- or pre-capitalist societies is rarely realistic), and
both involve the way we make sense of
ourselves, or rather, the way we are made sense of by the discourses of our
culture.
One way in which we are made sense of is
described in screen theory by the phrase
"the positioning of the reading (or viewing) subject." We will be exploring the issues involved in the question of subjectivity in chapter
4: for the moment we need to note that the text
produces a socially located position that it invites
the viewer to occupy in order to understand it easily and unproblematically.
Thus the Hart to Hart segment invites the viewer to "be" white
American, male, and middle-class. Realism achieves this positioning of the reading subject through its form.
MacCabe (1981a) claims an
essential formal characteristic of realism is that it is always structured by a "hierarchy of discourses." By
this he means that a realistic
narrative will contain a range of different and often contradictory discourses, which are usually explicitly
recognized as such, but that these are low
down in the discursive hierarchy. Taking precedence over them is an "unwritten" and therefore unrecognized
discourse which tells the "truth," that is, it provides us (the reader-spectator) with a position of
all-knowingness from which we can
understand and evaluate the various discourses of the narrative. In fiction, this is provided by the
implied author, in film and television
by the filmic/televisual discourse through which the story is told; this comes down finally to how the camera and the
microphone represent the real and how
the editor puts the results together. Thus in the Hart to Hart segment
there is a discourse of heroes and a discourse of villains, but the televisual discourse (which we have already
analyzed into its elements of setting,
lighting, dialogue, music, etc.) gives us the means to understand and evaluate both discourses and set them in a
sense-making relationship to each other.
This unspoken, unrecognized discourse which MacCabe
calls the "metadiscourse"
gives us a more privileged position than either the hero/ine
or the villains. This position of spectatorial privilege from which the world makes perfect realistic sense MacCabe
calls "dominant specularity."
This position of privilege is, as the word
implies, one that is ideologically active. The Hart
to Hart segment attempts to position us as white, male, middle-class Americans, and by adopting this comfortable and
ideologically rewarded position we are not just
making easy sense of the text, we are reproducing
the dominant ideology in our reading practice and are thus maintaining and validating it. Ideology, according to Althusser (1971), is not an
abstract, stable set of ideas that we unconsciously adopt, but a practice: it
exists and works only through practices, and here we are concerned with the simultaneous and inseparable practices of making sense of the text and
thus of constituting ourselves as subjects-in-ideology. By this I refer to
the process whereby understanding the
realistic, obvious sense of the segment requires viewers to adopt the social position and thus the social
identity that the text has prepared for them. In this case it is that of the
white, middle-class male. In
doing this viewers are making a particular sense of themselves and of their social relations and are thus
actively participating in the practice of maintaining the dominant ideology.
Closely related to the hierarchy of discourses
and dominant specularity in MacCabe's theory is realism's inability to deal with the real as contradicнtory. Contradictions that may exist in reality are inevitably resolved
in realism by the discourse at the top of the
hierarchy. Colin McArthur (1981) argues against MacCabe here by citing an instance of television handling contradiction:
In Days of Hope, there is
a scene in which Pritchard, the gentlemanly Northern
coal owner, lectures Ben and the three arrested Durham miners on the excellence of the British tradition of peaceful, gradual and constituн tional reform while, in the background, the soldiers brought in to suppress dissent
in the coalfield indulge in bayonet practice. (p.
308)
MacCabe's (1981b) answer to
this clarifies the working of the hierarchy of discourses in the resolution of contradictions:
What McArthur here confuses is
the narrative's ability to state a contradicн tion which it has already resolved, and the narrative's
ability to produce a contradiction which
remains unresolved and is thus left for the reader to resolve
and act out. In other words while McArthur looks simply for contradiction in the text, we must look at how contradiction is produced
in the audience. In the example McArthur cites there
is a contradiction between what the mine-owner says
and what the picture shows. But this is exactly the classic realist form which
privileges the image against the word to reveal that
what the mine-owner says is false. In this manner our position of knowledge is guaranteed Ч we may choose to disagree with
what the narrative tells us but if it has already placed us in the position
where we are sure we are right, it has not
questioned the very construction of that position. (p. 312)
This televisual metadiscourse
which produces this position of "dominant specularity" for us uses a
number of formal devices developed by Hollywood for what Monaco (1977)
calls the "omniscient style" of the classic Hollywood realist film. This depends on motivated editing
(sometimes called continuity editing,
e.g. by Bordwell and Thompson 1986), and its
essential compoнnents, the
shot/reverse shot technique and the 180░ rule, the eyeline
match and the action match.
Motivated editing, which developed as the
classic Hollywood realist style, tries to make the
work of the editor and director as invisible as possible. In chapter 1 we have noted that extreme close-up is more likely to be used
to portray villains than heroes; this is not to
suggest that the man is a villain, but to
swing our sympathy away from him, to see him from Cagney's
point of view. Cagney,
at the beginning and ending of the scene (shots 3, 9), is shot in "normal" close-up. In shots 5 and 7, however, she is more
worried about him and about her feelings concerning
him, so the camera moves in slightly to convey this anxiety, but not far enough
for the shot to become an alienating extreme
close-up. The camera's attempt to position us physically and emotionally with Cagney is supported by the
lighting: the man's face is slightly less well lit than Cagney's, and her hair has back-lighting to give her a "halo" effect. Both of these are
standard conventions of realistic lighting used to position the viewer "with" one character and
"against" the other.
The metadiscourse of
television realism is giving Cagney's discourse hierнarchical
precedence over the man's, and makes the scene easily readable by us in our position of dominant specularity. It
works to defuse the contradictions in Cagney's experience by "explaining" to us her
suspicions of the man and of her feelings for him.
Our understanding of the scene is omniscient, and therefore hierarchically superior even to Cagney's.
Realism and
radicalism
The theory of realism that we have been following
so far is leading us to the conclusion that
realism is inevitably reactionary, it finally
represents the world to us in a way that
naturalizes the status quo. This provides us with a point of entry to the debate that has lasted for at least the last
twenty years about television's role in an
industrialized society. This debate focuses around the question of whose interests does television serve, and whose,
if any, are disadvantaged by it. It is a debate
that, in one form or another, underlies the whole
of this book.
For the moment I wish to confine it to the
relationship between realism and radicalism, and by radicalism I mean a
critical interrogation of the dominant ideology and
of the social system which it has produced and underpins; this entails an awareness of the inequalities and of the
arbitнrariness of late capitalism, which in turn
produces the desire to hasten social change and the
willingness to work for it.
Analytically it is convenient to identify two main foci of this
definition of radicalism, which correspond
roughly to our two ways of theorizing realism -via its content and via its form.
The clearest example of the debate is that
centered around the British television
mini-series Days of Hope in Screen in the late 1970s. The main participants were MacCabe and McArthur, though
Tribe and Caughie also made valuable contributions. Their articles have been
collected in Bennett et ai, 1981: pp. 285-352. Days of Hope was a series of
four television plays
that told the story of the rise of the British labor movement from 1916 to the General Strike of 1928 through
the experiences of three main fictional characters. It provoked numerous public complaints, which
fell into two main categories Ч those
objecting to the BBC's screening of "left-wing propaнganda" and those questioning the historical
accuracy of its details, whether of dress,
setting, or action. It is significant that the complaints brought together
questions of ideological truth or falsity and ones of realistic accuracy or inaccuracy. Ideology and realism are inseparable.
Tribe (1981) makes the point that the letters
from the public concerning the veracity of the
image - the clothes, the buttons, whether the army marched in threes or fours in 1916 - were not just concerned with
historical accuracy, but that this concern was itself an ideological practice
and related to the ideological work of the text:
It can be suggested that this
veracity of the image is the vehicle for the veracity
of the history that it constructs. This history is itself conceived as the
truth of a past, a set of political events that we can draw lessons from. The
project of Days of Hope is thus associated with the writing of a popular
history along historicist lines. This history
is however recognized as Truth by the
viewer not by virtue of the "facts" being correct, but because the image looks right. The recognition effect
"that's the way it was" is a product
not of the historicity of the plot but of the manipulation of the image. (p.
324)
The realisticness of
the image directly affects its believability and thus is a vital part of the cultural form through which the ideological practice operates.
Obviously, Days of Hope was a potentially
radical television drama, and was seen as unacceptably so by (presumably)
right-wing members of its audiences. Its radicalism lay in the way
it provided a realistic view of recent history
from a self-consciously left-wing political viewpoint: it thus conнformed perfectly to Williams's (1977) defining
characteristics of realism - it was
contemporary (or nearly), secular, socially extended, and explicitly political. It was broadcast in a capitalist
society, and it attempted to present a left-wing, critical view of that
society. So its content challenged the dominant ideology of the time,
and even its harshest political critics, of whom MacCabe
was the most articulate, allowed that it was
"progressive" if not radical. Its progressiveness lay in the way that
its content opposed the dominant ideology and its concomitant social system. But, according to MacCabe,
it failed to achieve the status of the radical because its form was that of
conventional dramatic realism.а MacCabe admits the
progressiveness of the content of Days of Hope, but finally condemns it politically because its potential
is defused by the way it
is made sense of and understood within the ideological frame of bourgeois capitalism as it is
activated by the drama's realistic form. This may seem a tortuous argument, and to understand its
more general theoretical
implications we need to go back to the notions of the hierarchy of discourses, of dominant specularity, of contradictions, and of transparency.
Realism for MacCabe is necessarily reactionary
because it proposes a notion of the "truth" that is seen as factual, not as a construct of
discourse and culture.
This "factual truth" is conveyed by the unspoken discourse at the top
of the hierarchy, which
he calls the metadiscourse, and which positions the viewer at the point from which this
truth is made to seem objective, adeнquate, and therefore natural:
The simple access to truth which is guaranteed by
the meta-discourse depends on a repression of its
own operations and this repression confers an
imaginary unity of position on the reader from which the other disнcourses in the film can be read.
(MacCabe 1981a: 310)
It is the transparency of the metadiscourse
(the "repression of its own operations")
that guarantees its truthfulness because it disguises its arbitнrariness and therefore its political effectivity.
It positions the viewer in "an imaginary
unity of position" which is a crucial point in MacCabe's
argument, for it is this that denies
contradictions, or rather provides a means of resolvнing contradictions that may be expressed lower in the discursive
hierarchy. The point is that realism resolves
contradictions and does not leave them unresolved
and reverberating in the reader. Unresolved, active contraнdictions working in the reader's consciousness would destroy the unified
position of dominant specularity,
and the complacent acceptance of omniscience that goes
with it, and produce instead discomfort, uncertainty, and an active desire to
think through these contradictions not just in textual terms
but in terms of the reader's social experience. This is the radical frame of
mind that is the necessary condition for the desire for social change. The crucial distinction is the one between contradictions in the text (which
realism can handle comfortably without disturbing
its reactionary entrenchнment) and
contradictions in the reader (which are a precondition for radicalнism, and which the form of realism can never produce).
In chapter 6 we will discuss an alternative, and
more productive, theory of contradictions in the text, one that emphasizes the
impossibility of resolving them finally. MacCabe's theory stresses the power of realism, even when dealing
with radical content, to leave viewers always in a reactionary frame of mind because its form enables them to use the
dominant ideology to make dominant
sense of a radical movement and thus to defuse its radicalism.
Realism, in this view, is a reactionary mode of
representation that proнmotes and naturalizes
the dominant ideology. It works by making everything appear "realistic," and "realisticness"
is the process by which ideology is made to appear
the product of reality or nature, and not of a specific society and its culture. Thus, if the Hispanic villain in Hart to Hart had
triumphed over the white hero, it would, in
our society, have appeared "unrealistic." Similarly,
though differently, if the ship's cabin had had square windows instead
of portholes it would have appeared "unrealistic." Realism involves a fidelity both to the physical, sensually perceived details
of the external world, and to the
values of the dominant ideology. In this way ideology is mapped onto the objective world of "reality,"
and the accuracy of realism's represenнtation of the details of this
"real" world becomes the validation of the ideology it has
been made to bear - and I use the term "made to" in both its senses
of "constructed in order to" and
"required to." Realism's desire to "get the details right" is an ideological practice, for
the believability of its fidelity to "the
real" is transferred to the ideology it embodies. The conventions of realism have developed in order to disguise the constructedness of the "reality" it offers, and therefore of the arbitrariness of the
ideology that is mapped onto it.
Grounding ideology in reality is a way of making it appear unchallengeable and unchangeable, and thus is a
reactionary political strategy.