John Storey
CULTURAL STUDIES
AND THE STUDY OF
POPULAR CULTURE
AN INTRODUCTION
The aim
of this book is twofold: first, to introduce students and other interested
readers to the study of contemporary popular culture; and second, to suggest a
map of the development of cultural studies through a discussion of a range of
theories and methods for the study of popular culture. I have not attempted an
elaborate mapping of the field. Rather, my aim has been to bring together under
discussion a range of approaches which have made a significant contribution to
the development of the cultural studies approach to the study of contemporary
popular culture. It is hoped the book will provide a useful introduction - and
range of usable theories and methods -for students new to the field, and a
critical overview for those more familiar with the procedures and politics of
cultural studies.
1
CULTURAL
STUDIES AND POPULAR CULTURE
Cultural
studies is not a monolithic body of theories and methods. Stuart Hall (1992)
makes this very clear:
Cultural
Studies has multiple discourses; it has a number of different histories. It is
a whole set of formations; it has its own different conjunctures and moments in
the past. It included many different kinds of work ... It always was a set of
unstable formations ... It had many trajectories; many people had and have
different theoretical positions, all of them in contention. (278)
Cultural
studies has always been an unfolding discourse, responding to changing
historical and political conditions and always marked by debate, disagreement
and intervention. For example, in the late 1970s the centrality of class in
cultural studies was disrupted first by feminism's insistence on the importance
of gender, and then by black students raising questions about the invisibility
of race in much cultural studies analysis. It is simply not possible now to
think of cultural studies and popular culture, for example, without also
thinking about the enormous contribution to the study of popular culture made
by feminism. In the early 1970s, such a connection would have been far from
obvious.
Although
it is misleading - and probably not desirable - to limit cultural studies to an
academic orthodoxy, it is possible to present, for the purposes of an
introduction, some of its basic assumptions.
'Culture'
in cultural studies is defined politically rather than aesthetically. The
object of study in cultural studies is not culture defined in the narrow sense,
as the objects of aesthetic excellence ('high art'); nor culture defined in an
equally narrow sense, as a process of aesthetic, intellectual and spiritual
development; but culture understood as the texts and practices of everyday
life. This is a definition of culture which can embrace the first two
definitions; but also, and crucially, it can range beyond the social
exclusivity and narrowness of these, to include the study of popular culture.
Although cultural studies cannot (and should not) be reduced to the study of
popular culture, it is certainly the case that the study of popular culture is
central to the project of cultural studies.
Cultural
studies also regards culture as political in a quite specific sense - as a
terrain of conflict and contestation. It is seen as a key site for the
production and reproduction of the social relations of everyday life. Perhaps
the best-known elaboration of this way of seeing culture comes from Stuart Hall
(in Storey 1994). He describes popular culture, for example, as an arena of
consent and resistance. It is partly where hegemony arises, and where it is
secured. It is not a sphere where socialism, a socialist culture - already
fully formed - might be simply 'expressed'. But it is one of the places where
socialism might be constituted. That is why 'popular culture' matters. (466)
Others
within cultural studies might not express their attitude to popular culture
quite in these terms, but they would certainly share Hall's concern to think
culture politically.
Cultural
studies is grounded in Marxism. Marxism informs cultural studies in two
fundamental ways. First, to understand the meaning(s) of a cultural text or
practice, we .must analyse it in its social and historical conditions of
production and consumption. However, although constituted by a particular
social structure with a particular history, culture is not studied as a
reflection of this structure and history. History and culture are not separate
entities. It is never a question of reading a text or practice against its
historical background or using a text or practice to illustrate an already
formulated account of an historical moment - history and text/practice are
inscribed in each other and are embedded together as a part of the same
process. Cultural studies insists that culture's importance derives from the
fact that it helps constitute the structure and shape the history. As Hall (in
Storey 1996) explains, what cultural studies has helped me to understand is that
the media [for example] play a part in the formation, in the constitution, of
the things that they reflect. It is not that there is a world outside, 'out
there', which exists free of the discourses of representation. What is 'out
there' is, in part, constituted by how it is represented.
In other
words, cultural texts, for example, do not simply reflect history, they make
history and are part of its processes and practices and should, therefore, be
studied for the (ideological) work that they do, rather than for the
(ideological) work (always happening elsewhere) that they reflect. The second
assumption taken from Marxism is the recognition that capitalist industrial
societies are societies divided unequally along, for example, ethnic, gender,
generational and class lines. Cultural studies contends that culture is one of
the principal sites where this division is established and contested: culture
is a terrain on which there takes place a continual struggle over meaning, in
which subordinate groups attempt to resist the imposition of meanings which
bear the interests of dominant groups. It is this which makes culture
ideological.
Ideology
is without doubt the central concept in cultural studies. There are a number of
competing definitions of ideology, but it is the formulation established by
Hall (1985) which is generally accepted as the dominant definition within
cultural studies. Working within a framework of Antonio Gramsci's (1971: see
Storey 1993) concept of 'hegemony', Hall developed a theory of 'articulation'
to explain the processes of ideological struggle (Hall's use of 'articulation'
plays on the term's double meaning: to express and to join together). He argues
that cultural texts and practices are not inscribed with meaning, guaranteed
once and for all by the intentions of production; meaning is always the result
of an act of 'articulation' (an active process of 'production in use'). The
process is called 'articulation' because meaning has to be expressed, but it is
always expressed in a specific context, a specific historical moment, within a
specific discourse(s). Thus expression is always connected to and conditioned
by context. Hall also draws on the work of the Russian theorist Valentin
Volosinov (1973). Volosinov argues that meaning is always determined by context
of articulation. Cultural texts and practices are 'multiaccentual'; that is,
they can be articulated with different 'accents' by different people in
different contexts for different politics. Meaning is therefore a social
production; the world has to be made to mean. A text or practice or event is
not the issuing source of meaning, but a site where the articulation of meaning
- variable meaning(s) - can take place. And because different meanings can be
ascribed to the same text or practice or event, meaning is always a potential
site of conflict. Thus the field of culture is for cultural studies a major
site of ideological struggle; a terrain of 'incorporation' and 'resistance';
one of the sites where hegemony is to be won or lost.
In response
to the dual challenge represented by the undermining of the Marxist paradigm,
both by the events in Eastern Europe and the attacks of postmodern critics (see
McRobbie 1992,1994 and Stoнrey 1996), many in cultural studies have begun to
rethink its political project. Angela McRobbie's (1994) response to the
'crisis' in cultural studies is to argue for a return to neo-Gramscian hegemony
theory. She accepts that cultural studies has been radically transformed as
debates about postmodernism and postmodernity have replaced the more familiar
debates about ideology and hegemony. Cultural studies, she claims, has
responded in two ways. On the one hand, it has prompted a return to economic
reductive forms of analysis; and on the other, it has given rise to an
uncritical celebration of consumerism, in which consumption is understood too
exclusively in terms of pleasure and meaning-making. McRobbie rejects a return
'to a crude and mechanical base-superstructure model, and also the dangers of
pursuing a kind of cultural populism to a point at which anything which is
consumed and is popular is also seen as oppositional' (39). Instead, she calls
for 'an extension of Gramscian cultural analysis' (39), and for a return to
ethnographic cultural analysis which takes as its object of study '[t]he lived
experience which breathes life into [the] . . . inanimate objects [of popular
culture]' (27).
The
cultural studies use of hegemony theory - what Hall (1992) calls 'the
enormously productive metaphor of hegemony' (280) -at its best insists that
there is a dialectic between the processes of production and the activities of
consumption. The consumer always confronts a text or practice in its material
existence as a result of determinate conditions of production. But in the same
way, the text or practice is confronted by a consumer who in effect produces in
use the range of possible meaning(s), which cannot just be read off from the
materiality of the text or practice, or the means or relations of its
production.
Cultural
studies would also insist that making popular culture ('production in use') can
be empowering to subordinate and resistant to dominant understandings of the
world. But this is not to say that Popular culture is always empowering and
resistant. To deny the Passivity of consumption is not to deny that sometimes
consumption is passive; to deny that the consumers of popular culture are not
cultural dupes is not to deny that at times we can all be duped. But it is to
deny that popular culture is little more than a degraded culture, successfully
imposed from above, to make profit and secure ideological control. The best of
cultural studies insists that to decide these matters requires vigilance and
attention to the details of the production, distribution and consumption of
culture. These arej not matters that can be decided once and for all (outside
the, contingencies of history and politics) with an elitist glance and a
condescending sneer. Nor can they be read off from the moment of production
(locating meaning, pleasure, ideological effect, etc. in, variously, the
intention, the means of production or the production itself): these are only
aspects of the contexts for 'production in use', and it is, ultimately, in
'production in use' that questions of meaning, pleasure, ideological effect,
etc. can be (contingently) decided. Moreover, it is important to distinguish
between the power of the culture industries and the power of their influence.
Too often the two are conflated, but they are not necessarily the same.
Let me conclude
these introductory remarks with a long, but rewarding, quotation from the
American cultural studies theorist Lawrence Grossberg (1992b). In so many ways,
it sums up what I have been trying to say.
We have
to acknowledge that, for the most part, the relationнship between the audience
and popular texts is an active and productive one. The meaning of a text is not
given in some independently available set of codes which we can consult at our
own convenience. A text does not carry its own meaning or politics already
inside of itself; no text is able to guarantee what its effects will be. People
are constantly struggling, not merely to figure out what a text means, but to
make it mean something that connects to their own lives, experiences, needs and
desires. The same text will mean different things to different people,
depending on how it is interpreted. And different people have different
interpretive resources, just as they have different needs. A text can only mean
something in the context of the experience and situation of its particular audience.
Equally important, texts do not define ahead of time how they are to be used or
what functions they can serve. They can have different uses for different
people in different contexts . .. How a specific text is used, how it is
interpreted, how it functions for its audience - all of these are inseparably
connected through the audience's constant struggle to make sense of itself and
its world, even more, to make a slightly better place for itself in the world.
(52-3)
MORE
ABOUT THIS BOOK
My aim,
as stated earlier, is to present a range of theories and methods which have
been used within cultural studies to study contemporary popular culture. In the
main, I have tried to keep criticisms of the theories and methods to a minimum.
I have, thereнfore, tried to avoid 'opinion writing', where, instead of
explaining a theory or method, the author continually clutters his or her
account with talk of problems and how he or she would solve them or would do
the whole thing differently. There is of course a place for such an approach,
but I am not convinced that the appropriate place is an introductory text. I
would like the reader to take from this book an understanding of a range of
significant theories and methods, rather than an understanding of what I think
about them. Now it may, at times, become obvious what I think, but this should
not be the primary knowledge that the reader takes from the book. For much the
same reasons, I have quoted more than would be appropriate in a more 'advanced'
text. But I feel quite strongly that introductory texts work best when they
give their readers reasonable access to the theories and theorists under
discussion.
I am also
aware that I have simplified the field. Selection always means exclusion; and I
know that my selection will not meet with universal approval. There are other
valuable theories and methods which I have not discussed. In my defence, I can
say only that it is not possible in a book of this size to cover all the
theories and methods which have influenced cultural studies or which form part
of its very structure. I have, however, selected the approaches which I believe
are most significant.
In
conclusion, it is difficult to do full justice to the complexities of the
theories and methods that I have discussed. To really do justice' to the range
and diversity of the study of contemporary popular culture within cultural
studies would be the work of more than one book. Finally, whatever else this
book is, it is certainly not intended as a substitute for reading first-hand
the theories and methods discussed.
NOTES
1. For a
fuller version of this history, with particular reference to popular culture,
see Storey 1993, 1994 and 1996.
TELEVISION
Television
is the popular cultural form of the late twentieth century. It is without doubt
the world's most popular leisure activity. On the day you are reading this
book, there will be around the world in excess of 3.5 billion hours spent
watching1 television (Kubey and Csikszentmihalyi 1990: 1). British audiences,
for example, spend on average more than one-third of their waking hours
watching television. In the USA, average time spent viewing is about twice as
much (Allen 1992: 13). The 'average' American will spend in excess of seven
years watching television (Kubey and Csikszentimhalyi 1990: xi).
ENCODING
AND DECODING TELEVISUAL DISCOURSE
If we are
in search of a founding moment when cultural studies first emerges from
left-Leavisism, 'pessimistic' versions of Marxism, American mass communication
models, culturalism and structuralнism, the publication of Stuart Hall's
'Encoding and Decoding in the Television Discourse' (Hall 1973) is perhaps it. 2
In Hall's
model of televisual communication (see Figure 1), the circulation of 'meaning'
in televisual discourse passes through three distinctive moments: 'each has its
specific modality and conditions of existence' (128). First, media
professionals put into meaningful
9
televisual
discourse their particular account of, for example, a 'raw' social event. At
this moment in the circuit, a range of ways of looking at the world
('ideologies') are 'in dominance'.
programme as
'meaningful' discourse
encoding meaning structures 1 аааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааа decoding
■ meaning sturctures 2
frameworks
of knowledge ааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааа frameworks
of knowledge
relations of productionааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааа relations
of productionааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааа ааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааа
technical infrastructureааа аааааааааа ааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааа technical
infrastructureааа аааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааааа ааааааааааааааааааааааа
Figure I
[The
moment of media production] is framed throughout by meanings and ideas;
knowledge-in-use concerning the routines of production, historically defined
technical skills, professional ideologies, institutional knowledge, definitions
and assumpнtions, assumptions about the audience and so on frame the
constitution of the programme through this production strucнture. Further,
though the production structures of television originate the television
discourse, they do not constitute a closed system. They draw topics,
treatments, agendas, events, personnel, images of the audience, 'definitions of
the situation' from other sources and other discursive formations within the
wider socio-cultural and political structure of which they are a differentiated
part. (129)
Thus the
media professionals involved determine how the 'raw' social event will be
encoded in discourse. However, in the second moment, once the meanings and
messages are in meaningful discourse, that is, once they have taken the form of
televisual
10
discourse,
the formal rules of language and discourse are 'in dominance'; the message is
now open, for example, to the play of polysemy.
Since the
visual discourse translates a three-dimensional world into two-dimensional
planes, it cannot, of course, be the referнent or concept it signifies . ..
Reality exists outside language, but it is constantly mediated by and through
language: and what we can know and say has to be produced in and through
discourse. Discursive 'knowledge' is the product not of the transparent
representation of the 'real' in language but of the articulation of language on
real relations and conditions. Thus there is no intelligible discourse without
the operation of a code. (131)
Finally,
in the third moment, the moment of audience decoding, another range of ways of
looking at the world ('ideologies') are 'in dominance'. An audience is
confronted not by a 'raw' social event, but by a discursive translation of the
event. If the event is to become 'meaningful' to the audience, it must decode
and make sense of the discourse. 'If no "meaning" is taken, there can
be no "consumption". If the meaning is not articulated in practice,
it has no effect' (128). If an audience acts upon its decoding, this then
becomes itself a social practice, a 'raw' social event, available to be encoded
in another discourse. Thus, through the circulation of discourse, 'production'
becomes 'reproduction' to become 'production' again. The circuit starts in the
'social' and ends, to begin again, in the 'social'.
In other
words, meanings and messages are not simply 'transнmitted', they are always
produced: first by the encoder from the 'raw' material of everyday life;
second, by the audience in relation to its location in other discourses. Each
moment is 'determinate', operating in its own conditions of production.
Moreover, as Hall makes clear, the moments of encoding and decoding may not be
perfectly symmetrical. There is nothing inevitable about the outcome of the
process - what is intended and what is taken may not coincide. Media
professionals may wish decoding to correspond with encoding, but they cannot
prescribe or guarantee this. Governed by different conditions of existence,
encoding and decoding are
11
open to
variable reciprocity. There is always the possibility of misunderstanding.
No doubt
misunderstandings of a literal kind do exist. The viewer does not know the
terms employed, cannot follow the complex logic of argument or exposition, is
unfamiliar with the language, finds the concepts too alien or difficult or is
foxed by the expository narrative. But more often broadcasters are concerned
that the audience has failed to take the meaning as they - the broadcasters -
intended. What they really mean to say is that viewнers are not operating
within the 'dominant' or 'preferred' code. (135)
It is
this second 'misunderstanding' which interests Hall. Drawing on the work of
sociologist Frank Parkin (1971), he suggests 'three hypothetical positions from
which decodings of a televisual discourse may be constructed' (136). The first
position he calls 'the dominant-hegemonic position' (136). This occurs '[w]hen
the viewer takes the connoted meaning from, say, a television newscast or
current affairs programme full and straight, and decodes the message in terms
of the reference code in which it has been encoded, we might say that the
viewer is operating inside the dominant code' (136). To decode a television
discourse in this way is to be in harmony with the 'professional code' of the
broadcasters.
The
professional code is 'relatively independent' of the domiнnant code, in that it
applies criteria and transformational operations of its own, especially those
of a technico-practical nature. The professional code, however, operates within
the 'hegemony' of the dominant code. Indeed, it serves to reproduce the
dominant definitions precisely by bracketing their hegemonic quality and
operating instead with dis-i placed professional codings which foreground such
apparently neutral-technical questions as visual quality, news and presнentational
values, televisual quality, 'professionalism' and so on. (136)
12
The
dominant code is always articulated through the profesнsional code. David
Morley (1980) gives the example of the way in which Nationwide reported the
release of Patrick Meehan in 1976.
What is
'not relevant' as far as they are concerned is the whole political background
to the case. Now that is not to say that this is a straightforwardly ideologiнcal
decision to block out the political implications of the case. It's much more,
in their terms, a communicative decision, as it appears to them; that is their
notion of 'good television', to deal in that kind of 'personal drama'. (152)
The
second decoding position is 'the negotiated code or position' (137). This is
probably the majority position.
Decoding
within the negotiated version contains a mixture of adaptive and oppositional
elements: it acknowledges the legitimacy of the hegemonic definitions to make
the grand significations (abstract), while, at a more restricted, situational
(situated) level, it makes its own ground rules - it operates with exceptions
to the rule. It accords the privileged position to the dominant definitions of
events while reserving the right to make a more negotiated application to
'local conditions', to its own corporate positions. This negotiated version of
the dominant ideology is thus shot through with contradictions, though these
are only on certain occasions brought to full visibility. (137)
An
example of the negotiated code might be a worker who agrees in general terms
with the news report's claim that increased wages cause inflation, while
insisting on his or her right to strike for better pay and conditions.
Finally,
the third position identified by Hall is 'the opposiнtional code'. This is the
position occupied by the viewer who recognises the preferred code of the
televisual discourse but who nonetheless chooses to decode within an
alternative frame of reference. 'This is the case [for example] of the viewer
who
13
listens
to a debate on the need to limit wages but "reads" every mention of
the "national interest" as "class interest"" (138).
Hall
acknowledges that his hypothetical decoding positions 'need to be empirically
tested and refined' (136). This in part is the project of David Morley's The
'Nationwide' Audience (1980) - to test Hall's model, to see how individual
interpreнtations of televisual texts relate to socio-cultural background.
Morley provides a useful summary (and clarification of) his own working
understanding of Hall's encoding/decoding model as follows:
1.ааааааааааааааааааааааааа The production of a
meaningful message in the TV discourse is always problematic 'work'. The same
event can be encoded in more than one way. The study here is, then, of how and
why certain production practices and structures tend to produce certain
messages, which embody their meanings in certain recurring forms.
2.аааааааааааааааааааааааааа The message in
social communication is always comнplex in structure and form. It always
contains more than one potential 'reading'. Messages propose and preнfer
certain readings over others, but they can never become wholly closed around
one reading. They remain polysemic.
3.ааааааааааааааааааааааааа The activity of
'getting meaning' from the message is also a problematic practice, however
transparent and 'natural' it may seem. Messages encoded one way can always be
read in a different way. (10)
Morley
arranged for twenty-nine different groups to view two episodes (from 1976 and
1977) of the BBC's early-evening maga-zine/news programme Nationwide. The first
programme was shown to eighteen groups, the second to eleven. Each group
consisted of five to ten people. The groups were selected on the basis that
they might be expected to differ in their decodings from 'dominant' to
'negotiated' to 'oppositional'.
Figure 2
Morley
analysed the different readings produced by each group. Much of what he found
seemed to confirm Hall's model (see Figure 2 for Morley's diagrammatic
presentation of his findings). For example, a group of university arts students
and a group of teacher-training-college students produced readings which moved
between 'negotiated' and 'dominant', while the group of shop stewards produced
an 'oppositional reading'.3 However, when the middle-class bank managers and
the working-class apprentices both produced dominant readings, the correlation
between class and reading position looked less secure, forcing Morley to
15
acknowledge
that decodings are not determined 'directly from social class position'.
Rather, as he reformulates it: 'it is always a question of how social position
plus particular discourse positions produce specific readings; readings which
are structured because the structure of access to different discourses is
determined by social position' (134).
In this
way, Morley is able to explain the similarity in decodings between the
working-class apprentices and the middle-class bank managers in terms of the
formulation: determination of class plus other discourses (bodies of ideas and
shared socio-cultural practices which help constitute us as social subjects and
thus shape how we see and think about the world). Thus when we are
interpellated by a text, this is always in a context of other interpellations.
The text-reader encounter does not occur in a moment isolated from other
discourses, but always in a field of many discourses, some in harmony with the
text, some which are in contradiction with it. One reads, for example, as a
student, a Catholic, a socialist and a member of a youth subculture. Each
discourse may pull us in a different direction. Each may assume a different
level of importance in any given social setting. The response of the black
Further Education students and other predominantly black groups to Nationwide
-their 'critique of silence' - is therefore not to be explained as a failure of
communication (the technical inability of the encoders to get their message
across). Rather, what it demonstrates is the discourses of the text coming into
conflict with the discourses of the reader. 'Here', as Morley explains 'the
action of the cultures and discourses which these groups are involved in acts
to block or inflect their interpellation by the discourse of Nationwide' (143).
The converse is also evident in the decodings made by the working-class
apprentices. 'Here it is not simply a case of the absence of
"contradictory" discourses; rather it is the presence of other
discourses which work in parallel with those of the programme -enabling these
groups to produce "corresponding" representations' (143). Other
discourses are always in play, 'although their action is more visible when it
is a case of negative-contradictory rather than positive-reinforcing effect' (144).
As Morley explains:
[T]he
social subject is always interpellated by a number of discourses, some of which
are in parallel and reinforce each other, some of which are contradictory and
block or inflect the successful interpellation of the subject by other
discourses. Positively or negatively, other discourses are always involved in
the relation of text and subject, although their action is simply more visible
when it is a negative and contradictory rather than a positive and reinforcing
effect. (162)
However,
despite these other determinations (these other disнcourses), Morley still
stresses the importance of class in that it determines access (or the nature of
access) to different discourses. As he explains, 'the subject's position in the
social formation structures his or her range of access to various discourses
and ideological codes' (158). This then explains the correlation between the
readings made by the bank managers and the apprentices. The bank managers
produced a dominant reading because of their political commitment to the
conservatism of Nationwide's discourse, while the apprentices accepted it
uncritically because of a lack (unlike the shop stewards) of an alternative
political discourse. Class was the key to both readings. The first was made on
the basis of 'class interest', the second on the basis of the 'class interest'
of the British education system (the working-class apprentices were schooled to
be politically uncritical).
In the
'Afterword' to The 'Nationwide' Audience, Morley sums up (rather too modestly,
in my opinion) the achievements of his research:
I have
been able to do no more than to indicate some of the ways in which social
position and (sub)cultural frameworks may be related to individual readings. To
claim more than that, on the basis of such a small sample, would be misleading.
Similarly, I would claim only to have shown the viability of an approach which
treats the audience as a set of cultural groupings rather than as a mass of
individuals or as a set of rigid socio-demographic categories. Clearly, more
work needs to be done on the relation between group and individual readings.
(163)
17
Regretting
the absence from his research of any discussion of how the context of decoding
might effect the decodings produced, Morley's next research (1986) was an
exploration of television viewing in the family home.4
TELEVISION
AND 'THE IDEOLOGY OF MASS CULTURE'
In the
early 1980s, the Dutch cultural critic Ien Ang placed the following
advertisement in Viva, a Dutch women's magazine: 'I like watching the TV serial
Dallas, but often get odd reactions to it. Would anyone like to write and tell
me why you like watching it too, or dislike it? I should like to assimilate
these reactions in my university thesis. Please write to ... (1985: 10).
The
context for Ang's research was the emergence of the American 'prime-time soap'
Dallas as an international success (watched in over ninety countries) in the
early 1980s. In the Netherlands, Dallas was regularly watched by 52 per cent of
the population.
Following
the advertisement, Ang received forty-two letters (thirty-nine from women or
girls) from both lovers and haters of Dallas. These form the empirical basis of
her study of the pleasure(s) of watching Dallas for its predominantly female
audience. She is not concerned with pleasure understood as the satisfaction of
an already pre-existent need, but 'the mechanisms by which pleasure is aroused'
(9). Instead of the question 'what are the effects of pleasure?' she poses the
question 'what is the mechanism of pleasure; how is it produced and how does it
work?'
For Ang's
letter-writers the pleasure or displeasures of Dallas are inextricably linked
with questions of 'realism'. The extent to which a letter-writer finds the
programme 'good' or 'bad' is determined by whether they find it 'realistic'
(good) or 'unrealistic' (bad). Critical of both 'empiricist realism' (a text is
considered realistic to the extent it adequately reflects that which exists
outside itself) and 'classic realism' (Colin McCabe's (1974) claim that realism
is an illusion created by the extent to which a text can successfully conceal
its constructedness), Ang contends that Dallas is best understood as an example
of what she calls 'emotional realism'. Accordingly, Dallas can be read on two
levels: the level of denotation (the literal content of the programme, general
storyline, character interactions, etc.) and the level of connotation (the
associations and implications which resonate from the storyline and character
interactions, etc.).
It is
striking; the same things, people, relations and situations which are regarded
at the denotative level as unrealistic, and unreal, are at the connotative
level apparently not seen at all as unreal, but in fact as 'recognizable'.
Clearly, in the connotative reading process the denotative level of the text is
put in brackets. (42)
Viewing
Dallas, like any other programme, is a selective process, reading across the
text from denotation to connotation, weaving our sense of self in and out of
the narrative. As one letter-writer says: '[d]o you know why I like watching
it? I think it's because those problems and intrigues, the big and little
pleasures and troubles occur in our own lives too ... In real life I know a
horror like J.R., but he's just an ordinary builder' (43). It is this ability
to connect our own lives with the lives of a family of Texan millionaires which
gives the programme its emotional realism. We may not be rich, but we have
other fundamental things in common: relationships and broken relationships,
happiness and sadness, illness and health. Those who find it realistic shift
the focus of attention from the particularity of the (denotative) narrative to
the generality of its (connotative) themes.
Given the
way that Dallas plays with the emotions in an endless game of musical chairs in
which happiness inevitably gives way to misery, Ang calls this a 'tragic
structure of feeling' (46). As one letter-writer told her: '[s]ometimes I
really enjoy having a good cry with them. And why not? In this way my other
bottled-up emotions find an outlet' (49). Viewers who 'escape' in this way are
not so much engaging in 'a denial of reality as playing with it ... [in a] game
that enables one to place the limits of the fictional and the real under
discussion, to make them fluid. And in that game an imaginary participation in
the fictional world is experienced as pleasurable' (49). Whatever else is
involved, part of the pleasure(s) of Dallas is quite clearly connected to the
amount
19
of
fluidity which viewers are able or willing to establish between its fictional
world and the world of their day-to-day existence. But how does Dallas
construct this tragic structure of feeling? Ang's answer is that it is 'the
combination of melodramatic elements and the narrative structure of soap opera
that evokes a tragic structure of feeling' (78). In order to activate this
structure of feeling, it is necessary to have the cultural capital to take up a
reading formation informed by what she calls (following Peter Brooks (1976))
the 'melodramatic imagination'. The melodramatic imagination is the
articulation of a way of seeing beyond the grand human suffering of classical
tragedy, to ordinary day-to-day existence, with its own pain and triumphs, its
own victories and defeats, as itself profoundly j meaningful and significant.
It offers a means of organising reality, cut loose from the certainties of
religion, into meaningful contrasts and conflicts. As a narrative form
committed to melodrama's emphatic contrasts, conflicts and emotional excess,
Dallas is well placed to give sustenance to and make manifest the melodramatic
imagination. For those who see the world in this way (Ang claims that it
demands a cultural competence most often shared by women), 'the pleasure \ of
Dallas ... is not a compensation for the presumed drabness of daily life, nor a
flight from it, but a dimension of it' (83).
The
melodramatic imagination activates what is perceived in the text as a tragic
structure of feeling, which in turn produces the pleasure of emotional realism.
As the melodramatic imagination is in effect a 'reading formation' (see chapter
3 below), it follows that not all viewers of Dallas will take up this
particular reading position. On the basis of the letters, Ang is able to
separate the viewers into three reading positions connected by what she calls
'the ideology of mass culture' (15). The ideology articulates (using the word
in the Gramscian double sense to mean both to express and to form a
relationship with) the view that popular culture is the product of capitalist
commodity production and is therefore subject to the laws of the capitalist market
economy; the result of which is the seemingly endless circulation of degraded
commodities, whose only real significance is that they make a profit for their
producers. The ideology of mass culture, like any ideological discourse, works
by interpellating individuals into specific subject positions. The letters
suggest three positions from which to consume Dallas: as fans, as ironical
viewers, and as those who strongly dislike the programme.
Those
letter-writers who strongly dislike Dallas draw most clearly on the ideology.
They use it in two ways: to locate the programme negatively as an example of
'mass culture', and as a means to account for and support their dislike of the
programme. As Ang puts it, 'their reasoning boils down to this: "Dallas is
obviously bad because it's mass culture, and that's why I dislike it" '
(95-6). In this way, the ideology both comforts and reassures: 'it makes a
search for more detailed and personal explanations superfluous, because it
provides a finished explanatory model that convinces, sounds logical and
radiates legitimacy' (96). This is not to say that it is wrong to dislike
Dallas, only that professions of dislike are often made without thinking - in
fact, with a confidence born of uncritical thought.
It is
possible to like Dallas and still subscribe to the ideology of mass culture.
The contradiction is resolved by 'mockery and irony' (97). Dallas is subjected
to an ironising and mocking commentary in which it 'is transformed from a
seriously intended melodrama to the reverse: a comedy to be laughed at.
Ironising viewers therefore do not take the text as it presents itself, but
invert its preferred meaning through ironic commentary' (98). In this
construction, the pleasure of Dallas derives from the fact that it is bad:
pleasure and bad mass culture are reconciled in an instant. As one of the
letter-writers puts it: 'Of course Dallas is mass culture and therefore bad,
but precisely because I am so well aware of that I can really enjoy watching it
and poke fun at it' (100). For both the ironising viewer and the hater of
Dallas, the ideology of mass culture operates as a bedrock of common sense,
making judgements obvious and self-evident. Although both are trapped in the
normative standards of the ideology, the difference between them is marked by
the question of pleasure. On the one hand, the ironisers can have pleasure
without guilt in the sure and declared knowledge that they know that mass
culture is bad. On the other hand, the haters, although secure in the same
knowledge, can, nevertheless, suffer 'a conflict of feelings if, in spite of
this, they cannot escape its seduction' (101).
21
Finally,
there are the fans, those who love Dallas. For the viewers who occupy the
previous two positions, to actually like Dallas without resort to irony is to
be identified as someone duped by mass culture. As one letter-writer puts it:
'The aim is simply to rake in money, lots of money. And people try to do that
by means of all these things - sex, beautiful people, wealth. And you always
have people who fall for it' (103). The claim is presented with all the
confidence of having the full weight of the ideology's discursive support. Ang
analyses the different strategies which the fans of Dallas must use to deal
consciously and unconsciously with such condescension. The first strategy is to
'internalise' the ideology; to acknowledge the 'dangers' of Dallas, but to
declare one's ability to deal with them in order to derive pleasure from the
programme. Another strategy is to confront the ideology of mass culture as this
letter-writer does: 'Many people find it worthless or without substance. But I
think it does have substance' (105). But, as Ang points out, the writer remains
firmly within the discursive constraints of the ideology as she attempts to
reloнcate Dallas in a different relationship to the binary oppositions with
substance/without substance, good/bad. 'This letter-writer "negotiates' as
it were within the discursive space created by the ideology of mass culture,
she does not situate herself outside it and does not speak from an opposing
ideological position' (106). Finally, there is a letter which reveals a third
strategy of defence against the normative standards of the ideology of mass
culture. Like the second category of viewer, the ironist, this involves the use
of surface irony; only this time irony is used to justify what is in all other
respects a form of non-ironic pleasure. In this strategy, irony is used to
condemn the characters as 'horrible' people, while at the same time demonнstrating
an intimate knowledge of the programme and a great involvement in its narrative
development and character interacнtions, etc. She is caught between the
dismissive power of the ideology and the pleasure which she obviously derives
from watching Dallas. Her letter seems to suggest that she adheres to the
former when viewing with friends, and to the latter
when viewing
alone (and perhaps secretly when viewing with friends). As Ang explains, 'irony
is here a defence mechanism with which this letter-writer tries to fulfil the
social norms set by the ideology of mass culture, while secretly she
"really" likes Dallas' (109).
As Ang
shows, the fans of Dallas find it necessary to locate their pleasure in
relation to the ideology of mass culture; they 'internalise' the ideology; they
'negotiate' with the ideology; they use 'surface irony' to defend their
pleasure against the withering dismissal of the ideology. What all these
strategies of defence reveal is 'that there is no clear-cut ideological
alternative which can be employed against the ideology of mass culture - at
least no alternative that offsets the latter in power of conнviction and
coherence' (109-10). The struggle therefore, as so far described, between those
who like Dallas and those who dislike it, is an unequal struggle between those
who argue from within the discursive strength and security of the ideology of
mass culture, and those who resist from within (for them) its inhospitable
confines. 'In short, these fans do not seem to be able to take up an effective
ideological position - an identity -from which they can say in a positive way
and independently of the ideology of mass culture: "I like Dallas because
. . ." ' (110). There is, however, one final viewing position as revealed
in the letters; one that might help these fans: that is, one informed by the
ideology of populism. At the core of this ideology is the belief that one
person's taste is of equal value to another person's taste. As one
letter-writer puts it: 'I find the people who react oddly rather ludicrous -
they can't do anything about someone's taste. And anyway they might find things
pleasant that you just can't stand seeing or listening to' (113). The ideology
of populism insists that as taste is an autonomous category, continually open
to individual inflection, it is absolutely meaningless to pass aesthetic
judgements on other people's preferences. Given that this would seem to be an
ideal ideology from which to defend one's pleasure in Dallas, why do so few of
the letter-writers adopt it? Ang's answer is that it is to do with the
ideology's extremely limited vocabulary. After one has repeated 'there's no
accounting for taste' a few times, the argument begins to appear rather
limited. Compared to this, the ideology of mass culture has an extensive and
elaborate range of arguments and theories. Little wonder, then, that when
invited to explain why they like or dislike Dallas, the letter-writers find it
difficult to escape the normative ideological discourse of mass culture.
Cultural
studies, especially feminist cultural studies, must, accordнing to Ang, break
with the ideology of mass culture. She sees pleasure as the key concept in a
transformed feminist cultural politics. Feminist cultural studies must struggle
against 'the paternalism of the ideology of mass culture ... [in which w]omen
are . .. seen as the passive victims of the deceptive messages of soap operas .
.. [their] pleasure . . . totally disregarded' (118-19). Pleasure should not be
condemned as an obstruction to the feminist goal of women's liberation. The
question which Ang poses is: can pleasure through identification with the women
of 'women's weepies' or the emotionally masochistic women to soap operas 'have
a meaning for women which is relatively independent of their political
attitudes?' (133). Her answer is yes: fantasy and fiction do not function in
place of, but beside, other dimensions of life (social practice, moral or
political consciousness). It ... is a source of pleasure because it puts
'reality' in parenthesis, because it constructs imaginary solutions for real
contradictions which in their fictional simplicity and their simple
fictionality step outside the tedious complexity of the existing social
relations of dominance and subordinaнtion. (135)
Of course
this does not mean that representations of women do not matter. They can still
be condemned for being reactionary in an ongoing cultural politics. But to
experience pleasure from them is a completely different issue: 'it need not
imply that we are also bound to take up these positions and solutions in our
relations to our loved ones and friends, our work, our political ideals and so
on' (135).
Fiction
and fantasy, then, function by making life in the present pleasurable, or at
least livable, but this does not by any means exclude radical political
activity or consciousness. It does not follow that feminists must not persevere
in trying to produce new fantasies and fight for a place for them ... It does,
however mean that, where cultural consumption is concerned, no fixed standard
exists for gauging the 'progress-iveness' of a fantasy. The personal may be
political, but the personal and the political do not always go hand in hand.
(135-6)
THE TWO
ECONOMIES OF TELEVISION
John
Fiske (1987) argues that cultural commodities - including television - from
which popular culture is made circulate in two simultaneous economies: the
financial and the cultural. The financial economy is primarily concerned with
exchange value, the cultural is primarily focused on use - 'meanings,
pleasures, and social identities' (311). There is of course continual
interaction between these separate but related economies. Fiske gives the
example of Hill Street Blues. The programme was made by MTM and sold to NBC,
which then made a sponsorship deal with Mercedes Benz - in effect making the
audience for Hill Street Blues available to Mercedes Benz. This all happened in
the financial economy. In the cultural economy, the series changed from a
cultural commodity (to be sold to NBC) to a site for the production of meanings
and pleasures for its audience. In the same way, the audience changed from
commodity (to be sold to Mercedes Benz) to a producer of meanings and
pleasures.
Fiske
insists 'that the power of audiences-as-producers in the cultural economy is
considerable' (313). The power of the audience 'derives from the fact that
meanings do not circulate in the cultural economy in the same way that wealth
does in the financial' (313). While it is possible to possess wealth, it is
much harder to possess meanings and pleasures. In the cultural economy - unlike
in the financial economy - commodities do not move in a linear fashion
25
from
production to consumption; pleasures and meanings circulate without any real
distinction between production and consumption. Moreover, the power of the
consumer becomes manifest in the failure of producers to predict what will
sell. 'Twelve out of thirteen records fail to make a profit, TV series are axed
by the dozen, expensive films sink rapidly into red figures (Raise the Titanic
is an ironic example - it nearly sank the Lew Grade empire)' (313).
In an
attempt to offset the failures, the culture industries produce 'repertoires' of
goods in the hope of attracting an audience. But audiences constantly engage in
what Fiske calls - borrowing from Michel de Certeau (1984) - 'semiotic guerilla
warfare' (316). Whereas the culture industries seek to incorporate audiences as
commodity consumers, the audience often excorporates a television text, for
example, for its own purposes. Fiske cites the example of the way in which
Australian Aboriginal viewers appropriated Rambo as a figure of resistance,
relevant to their own political and cultural struggles. He also cites the
example of Russian Jews watching Dallas in Israel and reading it as
'capitalism's self-criticism' (320).
Fiske
argues that resistance to the power of the powerful by those without power in
Western societies takes two forms, semiotic and social. The first is mainly
concerned with meanings, pleasures and social identities; the second, with
transformations of the socio-economic system. He contends that 'the two are
closely related, although relatively autonomous' (316). Popular culture
operates mostly, 'but not exclusively', in the domain of semiotic power. It is
involved in 'the struggle between homogenisation and difference, or between
consensus and conflict' (316). In this sense, popular culture is a semiotic battlefield
in which a conflict is fought out between the forces of incorporation and the
forces of resistance, between an imposed set of meanings, pleasures and social
identities, and the meanings, pleasures and social identities produced in acts
of semiotic resistance: 'the hegemonic forces of homogeneity are always met by
the resistances of heterogeneity' (Fiske 1989a: 8).
Fiske's
two economies operate in the interests of opposing
sides of
the struggle: the financial economy tends to favour the forces of incorporation
and homogenisation, while the cultural economy tends to favour the forces of
resistance and difference. Semiotic resistance - in which dominant meanings are
challenged by subordinate meanings - has the effect of undermining capitalнism's
attempt at ideological homogeneity. In this way, according to Fiske, the
dominant class's intellectual and moral leadership is challenged.
Fiske's
approach to popular culture - including television - is one which recognises
popular culture as 'a site of struggle' and, while acknowledging 'the power of
the forces of dominance', chooses instead to direct its attention to 'the
popular tactics by which these forces are coped with, are evaded or are
resisted'. In other words, '[i]nstead of tracing exclusively the processes of
incorporation, it investigates rather that popular vitality and creativity that
makes incorporation such a constant necessity' (20). Moreover, 'instead of
concentrating on the omnipresent, insidious practices of the dominant ideology,
it attempts to understand the everyday resistances and evasions that make that
ideology work so hard and insistently to maintain itself and its values'. His
approach 'is essentially optimistic, for it finds in the vigour and vitality of
the people evidence both of the possibility of social change and of the
motivation to drive it (20-1).
NOTES
1.ааааааааааааааааааааа David Morley's Family
Television (1986) discusses how television is in ways which render the term
'watching television' rather inadequate.
2.аааааааааа ааааааааааThe essay was first presented as a
paper to The Council of Europe Colloнquy on 'Training in Critical Reading of
Television Language', September 1973, and subsequently published as Centre for
Contemporary Cultural Studies Stencilled Occasional Paper no. 7 in the same
year. The diagram (Figure 1) and quotations are from Hall's 1980 revised
version (Hall et al. 1980).
3.ааааааааааааааааааааа One interesting problem
about the model is the way in which it seems always to assume encoding from a
dominant position. What happens to the model when the encoded message is
'radical' or 'progressive'? See Dyer (1977).
4.ааааааааа ааааааааааааSince the publication of The
'Nationwide' Audience, Morley has sought to both clarify and modify its
theoretical and methodological claims.
For
details see Morley 1980, 1986, 1992. For critical commentaries on the
encoding/decoding model, and on Morley's use of it, see Ang 1989, Grossberg
1983, Jancovich 1992, Lewis 1983, Moores 1993, Turner 1990. See Cruz and Lewis
1994 for an interview with Stuart Hall on the encoding/decoding model.